REVITALIZING
THE LAW AND DEVELOPMENT MOVEMENT
A
Case Study on Land Law In Thailand
PHLIP
VON MEHREN, J.D. |
TIM
SAWERS, J.D. |
MILBANK,TWEED,HADLEY
AND McCLOY
WASHINGTON, D.C. |
HODGSON,
RUSS, ANDREWS, WOODS & GOODYEAR
BUFFALO, N.Y. |
|
Within
the framework of his analytical system, which is characterized by the
use of ideal types, by examination of the spread of rationalism, and by
a normative assumption about the advanced nature of capitalism(10),
Weber espoused a typology with four categories of legal thought.(11) He used a typology to isolate by juxtaposition the unique features of
Western Law.
The
first type, "formal irrational," is characteristic of systems
that depend on primitive procedures for deciding disputes, such as the
Delphic oracle in ancient Greece. Stringent observance of procedural rules
is of utmost importance, but the rules have no relationship to the rational
determination of the rights and liabilities of the parties in the particular
case. One imagines a priest examining the viscera of a goat and proclaiming
the guilt or innocence the accused.
A second
type of legal system is the "substantively irrational." Kronman
cites as an example "khadi-justce" of the Mideast. Weber characterizes
these systems as using an ad hoc process to determine the outcome
of a particular case. The system is "irrational" because it
espouses no general rules; it is "substantive" because of its
willingness to consider the widest range of considerations in determining
the outcome of a case. The picture of a Bedouin chief handing out rough-and-tumble
justice springs to mind.
The
third type of judicial system is "substantively rational." This
type is exemplified by theocratic or patriarchal legal systems. These
systems are "rational" in the sense of adherence to fixed principles
rather than in their mode of thought.
The
final type is called "formally rational" and corresponds to
the European model of legal thought. These systems give precedence to
the general over the particular and to the secular over the moral. Formally
rational systems stress "the logical analysis of meaning" which
corresponds to the view that law contains neutral principles which are
discoverable through the application of techniques of legal reasoning.(12) The European system is also characterized by differentiation of roles
within law, and between law and politics.(13)
According
to Kronman and Trubek an apparent problem or contradiction emerges in
Weber's discussion of "formal rationality."(14) They argue that Weber's own definition of "formal rationality"
led him to find its highest expression in the Pandectist system of Germany.
Thus, if "formal rationality" in law is an important variable
in capitalist development, the more strongly it manifests itself, the
sooner and more successful capitalist development should be. Yet England
was the first country to develop capitalism and was significantly ahead
of the continent economically until the post World War period. The inability
of Weber to solve the so called "English problem" is a central
tension that both Kronman and Trubek see as undermining his analysis of
law's relationship to capitalist development. Yet, at least two solutions
to the apparent contradictions are possible. Ewing argues that Kronman
and Trubek misinterpreted Weber. She suggests that a one-to-one correspondence
between economic and legal rationality is not an underlying assumption
of Weber's schema.(15) Thus, the most rational
legal system is not necessarily the most economically successful. Essentially
this argument rests on an analysis which recognizes the relevance of several
independent variables in the rise of capitalism but realizes that the
relative mix and importance of these variables may vary from case to case.
Thus, even if England did have a less rational legal system, other variables,
e.g. religion, could have been stronger than on the Continent or its legal
system could have been more rational at an earlier point in time. Yet
Ewing essentially takes another tack to untangle the contradiction:
a
legal order is formally rational in the sociological rather than
the juridical sense when it is based on formal justice. Such a system
is abstract and bound by strict procedures, and guarantees the legal
certainty essential for calculability in economic transactions, all
of which applies both to civil and common law countries.(16)
Ewing's
analysis successfully saves Weber's conceptual schema from Kronman's and
Trubek's more pessimistic interpetation by distinguishing between formal
rationality in the sociological and in the juridical sense. Thus the doctrinal
drive for meta-rationality in the Civil Law is viewed as irrelevant, or
at least not totally determinative, to the relationship between legalism
and capitalism. Both the civil and common law systems provide a context
of certainty and predictability sufficient for capitalist activity. Thus,
the so called "English problem" is a red herring.
Ewing's
analysis essentially preserves the coherence of Weber. She has convincingly
shown that Weber can be fairly construed so as to preserve the theoretical
integrity of his framework from the alleges contradictions uncovered by
Kronman and Trubek. Given that Weber's framework is coherent, how did
he view the specific causal interaction between law and social change?
Kronman has called Weber's approach "causal agnosticism."(17) Yet he points to two different ways in which Weber claimed that "formally
rational" law could influence capitalist development. The first is
both the most important and the most general. Legal rules that protect
individual entitlements, especially in the context of contracts, promote
economic activity:
By
guaranteeing that contracts will be enforced in accordance with fixed
rules known in advance by the contracting parties, the legal order significantly
increases the probability that promises, once made, will be kept and
thereby encourages promisemaking and the forms of economic activity
that depend on it (most importantly, market exchange).(18)
The
legal order also promotes capitalism through the development of concepts
that are useful in certain specific situations. Weber specifically mentioned
title in this regard. Business organizations require "a method by
which transfers can be made legally secure [while eliminating] the need
of constantly testing the title of the transferor."(19) These concepts serve to solve the practical problems that foster economic
development.
Yet
Weber did not view the relationship between law and capitalism as merely
the former affecting the latter. He also saw the economic order affecting
law. As Trubek explains, "Legalism supported the development of capitalism
by providing a stable and predictable atmosphere: capitalism encouraged
legalism because the bourgeoisie were aware of their own need for this
type of governmental structure."(20) Legalism and capitalism could be both cause and effect for each other.
Furthermore, the specific relationship between law and development seems
to vary with the given historical case.
Weber's
conclusions regarding both the relationship between law and capitalism,
as well as what legalism requires, provide a framework for the study of
law's role in social change on a comparative basis. In the context of
the emergence of Thai concepts of title, Weberian analysis offers several
clear propositions. The first is that there is a relationship between
the development of formally rational law and capitalist development. Formally
rational law is characterized, in the sociological sense, by (1) the emergence
of formal justice, composed of strict procedures, and the use of legal
reasoning applied through logical procedures to the facts of the case,
and (2) the differentiation of legal from purely political institutions,
as well as the differentiation within the legal profession of various
functions. The second proposition is that formal justice can have an impact
on capitalism in two ways. The first is the general effect of predictability
and calculability that formal justice provides capitalists. The second
is the proclivity for a formal system of justice to solve practical legal
problems through the elaboration of specific legal concepts, such as title
to land, which function to foster capitalist development. The third proposition
is that a causal relationship exists between the development of formally
rational law and capitalism but that the exact relationship is problematic,
and may depend on the specific historic context. The second and third
chapters of this paper will explore these propositions on the basis of
Thai legal and economic development.
Part
3
Endnotes:
(10)
Many analysts have criticized modern sociologists who have followed Weber's
lead in using ideal types as a framework for analyzing development in
Third World countries. See Portes, "Modernity and Development: A
Critique" in Studies in Comparative International Development 3 (1973). It is interesting that most of the new sociological literature
on development has been based on structural or Marxian analysis of underdevelopment.
(11)
See A. Kronman, supra note 5, at 76-79. I draw heavily here on
Kronman's description of Weber's typology.
(12)
See Trubek, supra note 5, at 927-933. Trubek claims that a central
contradiction exist in the discussion of "the logical interpretation
of meaning" between Weber as a positivist and as a "precursor
of what we today call 'critical legal studies'." While an interesting
view, perhaps the delphic qualities of Weber's writings have led Trubek
to impose his own ideas, sympathetic to a Critical Legal Studies perspective,
onto Weber.
(13)
Trubek, "Max Weber and the Rise of Capitalism," 3 Wis. L. Rev.
720, 724 (1972).
(14)
A. Kronman, supra note 5, at 87-92 and 120-124; Trubek, supra note 13, at 746.
(15)
Ewing, "Formal Justice and the Spirit of Capitalism: Max Weber's
Sociology of Law," 21 Law and Society Rev. 489 (1987).
(16) Id. at 489 (emphasis added).
(17)
See A. Kronman, supra note 5, at 126. Kronman argues that there
are two grounds on which Weber's agnosticism can be defended. The first
is that Weber is essentially pointing out the inadequacy of any theory
that attempts to account for the interaction between law and capitalism.
A second ground is that Weber essentially is arguing a historisist position
in which the causal interaction between law and capitalism varies with
the historical context. See id. at 129-130.
(18) Id. at 125.
(19)
Quoted in id. at 125.
(20)
Trubek, supra note 13, at 736-37. Note that the second portion
of this quote is entirely consistent with a Marxian analysis of social
change. |